The Archimedean Point: Theses 1-10

Book: Concrete Philosophy, vol 1
First Chapter

There is an Archimedean point, of which certainty is beyond our knowledge and is independent from us, but it is ontically and ontologically true: There is something.

We shall start from an analysis of such undeniable truth. If there was no mankind nor an intelligent being able to apprehend concepts, there would still have a real, absolutely assured, accurate, and true thought: There is something.

Mankind and the world – since contingents – could not exist. But there is something, since on the contrary there would be the absolute emptiness, the absolute and total absence of anything, the absolute nothingness. There is either something or the absolute nothingness.

Absolute nothingness would be the total absence of anything, ab-solutum, dis-connected from anything, total and absolute emptiness. At this very moment, we could be a dream or an illusion of a being, we could doubt of our experience and the exterior world. However, we could not affirm that there is nothing, since doubt itself and illusion itself affirm that there is something and not the absolute nothingness.

When one says there is something, one is affirming the presence of what is called being, even though not yet knowing what being is, what its essence is and what one can say about it. Therefore, there is something is a peremptory contradiction to absolute nothingness. To affirm absolute nothingness is to affirm that there is absolutely no thing. However, it is important to note the term absolute, since admitting that there is something is not contradictory to admitting that there is not something, since one thing could exist whilst something else could not. We shall refer to the first nothingness as absolute nothingness and the second nothingness as relative nothingness. If absolute nothingness contradicts there is something, relative nothingness only opposes it, but not excludes it, and, therefore, they can both happen, can both “pose” – both positive, but of inverse positivity.

Between there is something and absolute nothingness, there must be no doubt about the certainty of the first, which acceptance emerges from an intellectual act of complete adhesion and firmness, with no possibility of error. Where could the error be? If one affirms there is something, the only error could be that, in fact, there is not anything, which is denied even by the very act of such thought, by even the most skeptical act of thinking, since if there was nothing, there was not even the emergence of doubt.

Consequently, the affirmation there is something is apodictically demonstrated, so as, in the same extent, the impossibility of the absolute nothingness, since being true that there is something, there is absolutely no absolute nothingness; absolute nothingness is impossible, since there is something.

The first postulate of Concrete Philosophy is, therefore, apodictically demonstrated:

Thesis 1: There is something whilst there is not the absolute nothingness.
Thesis 2: Absolute nothingness, being impossible, cannot do anything.

Absolute nothingness would be the total and absolute absence of being, of power, since how what is not, what does not exist, what is nothing, could do something? In order to “do” something, it is necessary to previously “be” something. Therefore, absolute nothingness, besides from not being, is impossible and cannot do anything. Because if it could do anything, it would “be” something and not the absolute nothingness. However, we have verified that there is something and that the absolute nothingness cannot exist; therefore, we cannot expect anything from it, since it is nothing.

The corresponding verb to the Latin noun res (thing), reor, means to think or to believe. Thing, thus, would be that in what one can think or believe. Such term refers to the time-spatial concrete being, of which man has sensible intuition or of all that cannot predicate the absolute nothingness. The word something, which Latin origin aliquid is formed by aliud (other) and quid (what) – what is distinguished from other, what is distinct, a “thing” – and elucidates, after all, that something is understood as all that poses, happens and of what cannot be said as being a mere nothing. Now, absolute nothingness cannot happen, cannot “pose”, has no positivity; it is pure denial, total absence of any thing, of what can be said as being nothing.

Also the term entitas, entity, in its logos (in its intrinsic reason), means something to which the absolute nothingness cannot be predicated. And all that is not the absolute nothingness is something (aliquid), an entity (entitas). Therefore, everything that is not the absolute nothingness is something that happens, that “poses”, that occurs.

If there weren’t anything, we would have the total absence of any thing that poses, that happens. But, at the same time, one could not say that the absolute nothingness was, then, happening, since it was not posing, nor occurring: it would be the total absence. And it would suffice that anything happened, the presence of anything befell, to the absolute nothingness to become dismissed.

Mankind could not be what we believe it is, but still the absolute nothingness, the total and complete absence of anything, is not a possibility. Something is, happens, occurs. And what this something actually is should be our next subject.

In there is something, the subject completely “reflects” the verb, because outside “something” nothing can be, since nothingness is not and being is the being of something. Therefore, there is real and formal identity between “to be” and “something”, because “to be” is only so when refers to “something”, since nothingness is not. We shall deepen such statements through another ways opportunely.

Thesis 3: One can proves something by presenting it and not only by demonstrating it.

The concept of demonstration (de-monstrare) implies the concept of presenting something so to make another proposition evident, when compared to the first. The first certainty has, naturally, to be presented, since demonstration implies something previously given as absolutely certain. Therefore, the presentation (as in the act of presenting, showing something) suffices to prove the validity of something. The axiom there is something is evident per se and, as such, presents its validity, independent from human schematic – of which schematic contents can vary. There is something is evident and extra mentis (outer human mind).

Thesis 4: Demonstration demands a medium term; “presentation”, however, does not.

Demonstration demands a medium term because it is an operation consisting of comparing what one intends to prove to something else already proved. “Presentation” follows an intuitive mode. The evidence of what is presented is imposed by itself, since its denial would be incongruous. One can directly demonstrate by a mere comparison, as stated above; or indirectly, as a reduction ad absurdum, as in the second case. For instance, if there wasn’t anything, there would be the absolute nothing, which is absurd; therefore, something IS. Such is an indirect demonstration that there is something.

Thesis 5: There are non-deducted propositions, which are per se intelligible and per se evident (axioms)

It would suffice to merely present one example to validate such thesis. There is something and There isn’t the absolute nothingness have such requirements, what presents, therefore, the existence of non-deducted propositions (since they don’t require evidences other than themselves), per se evident , once including within itself a sufficient degree of certainty, indispensable to the axiom and dispensable of demonstration, since disregard comparison with other things in order to demonstrate their validity.

Thesis 6: Philosophy can be constructed with universally valid judgments.

It is common the statement that philosophy cannot be build on top of universally valid judgments. However, such statement is easily refuted, sufficing the establishment of a universally valid judgment whereupon, concretely, one can erect an entire philosophical system, as we shall do.

The theses, which were established as starting points to the foundation of our Concrete Philosophy, are universally valid. Only an appeal to foolishness, rebutted by the appeal itself, would consider the existence of absolute nothingness and not of something. Even such vain and fool statement would state the existence of something. We can doubt of own existence and regard ourselves as an illusion, but it would still be something. If we need ourselves to express an idea or to expose a philosophy, we don’t need ourselves so something exists, because even if we were illusion, we would be the illusion of something that exists. Therefore, such postulate doesn’t depend on us to present itself as evident. It is a universally valid judgment and shall be the foundation of Concrete Philosophy.

Thesis 7: Absolute nothingness is contradictory to there is something.

There is a contradiction when affirming the presence and, simultaneously, the absence of the same aspect in the same object. To say “there is something” is to contradict “there is the absolute nothingness”, since if there is something, the absolute nothingness is excluded. To say “there is the absolute nothingness” is to say “there is not something”, i.e., it is to contradict “there is something”.

Thesis 8: What is, is; is being. What is not is non-being.

Of what is, one can say that has being and is being. The concept of the word being is not definable, since to explain what being is we need the concept of being. But all that exists, is. Being, according to Suarez, is the “aptitude for existence”. To be is to be something, and not a mere nothingness (a total and absolute absence). Only the being can, since only the being has the aptitude to exist and the absolute nothingness, impossible and impotent, has no aptitude for anything, once it is not.

Non-being is what is not. Absolute nothingness is absolute non-being. If anything, one or another, is not, it does not affirm an absolute nothingness, but only that such or such thing is not, i.e., a relative nothingness. Absolute nothingness is an absolute non-being. Relative nothingness is a relative non-being. Postulating the first denies, total and absolutely, that something is. Postulating the second does not deny, total and absolutely, that something is, but only that such and such thing is not.

Accepting that something is does not deny, total and categorically, that something is not. Something is and something is not are two particular and sub-contrary judgments and the truth of one does not necessarily imply the falsity of another. Both can be true, as in fact they are.

Absolute nothingness is impossible, do not, since, in order to do, it is necessary to be. Something has to previously be something in order to do something. What is, occurs, we cannot call it nothing, but something, being. Therefore, what is not does not exist; and only what is, exists. We don’t know yet what this being is, but we know it is.

The term exist means that something effectively is, in the complete exercise of being, since what can become already is, in a certain way, or, in the contrary, would be the absolute nothingness, which is impossible. If something can come to happen, such thing is possible. If it is possible, it cannot come from absolute nothingness, which was already repelled, but from something that is, since nothingness – impossible and impotent – cannot create anything.

Therefore, we can reach the certainty of a final conclusion: There is something, which is, and exists.

There is no doubt that there is something, that something is. It shall be indubitable that something exists, that something is in the full exercise of its being, that is not merely a possibility, once we examine the following arguments:

If there was no thing in the full exercise of its being, we would have only a possible being, i.e., what is still a relative nothingness and shall become – or not – something in the full exercise of being. What is still a possibility is a being in other, because what can be, is, and, to can, has to be in the full exercise of its being, since how it could do something if it has no power?

Therefore, something exists, since, if it didn’t, it would be the possibility of some existing thing, or, in the contrary, it would be the absolute nothingness, which is impossible. Such thesis shall be demonstrated via a different approach later on.

Commentaries
There is something is an ontological truth

 

In logical truth, there is a correspondence between the mind and the thing, whilst, in ontological truth, there is a correspondence between the thing to which the idea in the mind correspond. Ontological truth is the revelation of the logos of the thing. The judgment there is something has such aptitude and capacity. The ontological truth results from the intrinsic analysis of the thing, which is fit and able to, by itself, reveal and allow an intelligent being of knowing such truth. There is something has, thus, characteristics not only of a logical, but of an ontological truth.

When ontologically considered, there is something is an immediate analytical proposition (per se notas), since something implies, at least, the existence of something, inasmuch as the habitudo (correlation) between subject and predicate are apprehended by analysis. When ontically considered, it would be, thus, a mediate analytical proposition (non per se notas), which knowledge results from human experience. Later on we shall consider under yet other aspects.

In both manners, the proposition there is something is necessary, by an ontological necessity and an ontical consequence. Such aspects fortify even more the apodicticy of the Concrete Philosophy fundamental thesis, which is necessarily evident by any way of intellectual investigation.

The term necessary comes from Latin necesse, and, etymologically, is formed by the negative ne and the verb cedere, with a sense of to go, to forego, to leave, to move away, and also, to give up, to renounce, to abandon. Therefore, the term necesse (necessity) indicates the content of what is not renounceable, of what is unpostponable, of what cannot be otherwise.

The search, within ontological-dialectic, for the nexus of necessity, is the search for the eidetic content of the have-to-be, the only one that can-and-must-be. Man has the ability to construct a variety of noetic-eidetic schemes. Those are the eide, abstractly constructed by our intellect (nous), through an operation (noesis), and its contents (noema) recreate – or not – what-is-bound-to-be and must-imperatively-be. To reach such necessary eidetic content is to reach the ontological content of a thing.

The first measure of ontological-dialectic is, therefore, to search such contents, renouncing all that can not-be, until reaching the non-cede-able. Moreover, the ontological content must arise from an analysis that presents a nexus of necessity. Such operation totally deviates from the mere opinion, since opinion is an affirmative of our mind about contingent things (or noetic-eidetic contents), that could or could not be. The ontological content is only true when all and any contingence is excluded, once discovered the ontological absurdity. To reach the ontological content of what is under scrutiny is, therefore, the primary measure for such dialectic, which, without it, the intended aim cannot be reached, i.e, the construction of universally valid judgments that, being ontologically true, totally diverge from all doxa (opinion).

Thesis 9: The proposition “there is something” is sufficiently evident by itself

 

The truth within “there is something” does not demand, to be noted, a special mind. It is noted per se – and sufficiently – since its denial would affirm the absolute nothingness, which is absurd. There is something does not demand –and could even dismiss – demonstration. If we gather them, it is only to fortify its objective evidence; and we say “objective evidence” because it is not a truth subjectively apprehended by adequacy, but per se sufficiently true.

Thesis 10: “There is something” is not only an entity of reason, but a real-real entity

It is considered entity of reason (ens rationis, cf. the scholastics) that of which the sole existence is in the human mind. For instance, relations, orderings and general notions. It is considered real entity that of what has an existence outside human mind (extra mentis). A real entity can also have an existential correspondence within human mind. Could there is something deserve an affirmation as being only an entity of reason? If there is something is a entity of reason, we can determine that it is not only so, but also a real entity, because if there is an entity of reason, something has to be the supporter of it. And if there is something can be intellected, there is [really] something, since there has to be something in order to something be intellected, proving, consequently, that there is something is a real-real entity. Such demonstration fortify even more the possibility of an apodictically founded, universally valid truth.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out / Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out / Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out / Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out / Change )

Connecting to %s